[1]
|
Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2004). Insensitive semantics. A defence of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell.
|
[2]
|
Cohen, P. (2006). If not Turing’s test, then what? AI Magazine, 26, 61-67.
|
[3]
|
Cole, D. (2009). The Chinese room argument. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition).
|
[4]
|
Copeland, B. J. (2001). The Turing test. Mind and Machines, 10, 519-539. doi:10.1023/A:1011285919106
|
[5]
|
French, R. (2000). The Turing test: The frst fifty years. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 115-121. doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01453-4
|
[6]
|
Harnad, S. (1991). Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. Mind and Machines, 1, 43-54.
|
[7]
|
Harnad, S. (2000). Mind, machines and Turing. The indistinguishability of the indistinguishable. Mind and Machines, 9, 425-445.
|
[8]
|
Hayes, P., & Ford, K. (1995). Turing test considered harmful. Proceedings of the 14th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. San Francisco: Morgam Kaufman Publishers.
|
[9]
|
Hayes, P., & Ford, K. (1997). Talking heads—A review of speaking minds: Interviews with twenty eminent cognitive scientists. AI Magazine, 18, 123-125.
|
[10]
|
Korta, K., & Perry, J. (2011). Critical pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
|
[11]
|
Guha, R., & McCarthy, J. (2003). Varieties of contexts. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, 2116, 290-303.
|
[12]
|
McCarthy, J. (1990). Formalizing commonsense. New York: Ablex.
|
[13]
|
Moor, J. H. (2001). The status and future of the Turing test. Mind and Machines, 11, 73-93. doi:10.1023/A:1011218925467
|
[14]
|
Moor, J. H. (2003) The Turing test. The elusive standard of artificial intelligence. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
|
[15]
|
Luger, G. F. (2005). Artificial intelligence: Structures and strategies for complex problem solving (5th ed.). Boston: Addison-Wesley.
|
[16]
|
Penco, C. (2010). Essentially incomplete descriptions. European Journal for Analytic Philosophy, 6, 47-66.
|
[17]
|
Penco, C., & Vignolo, M. (2005). Converging towards what? Pragmatic and semantic competence. In P. Bouquet, & L. Serafini (Eds.), Context representation and reasoning (Vol. 136). CEUR-WS.
http://sunsite.informatik.rwth-aachen.de/Publications/CEUR-WS/Vol-136/
|
[18]
|
Perry, J. (1997). Indexicals and demonstratives. In R. Hale, & C. Wright (Eds.), Companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 586-612). Oxford: Blackwell.
|
[19]
|
Rajaraman, V. (1997). Turing test and after. Resonance, 2, 50-59.
doi:10.1007/BF02835001
|
[20]
|
Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199230532.001.0001
|
[21]
|
Recanati, F. (2010). Truth conditional pragmatics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199226993.001.0001
|
[22]
|
Saygin, A. P., Cicekli, I., & Akman, V. (2000). Turing test: 50 years later. Mind and Machines, 10, 463-518.
doi:10.1023/A:1011288000451
|
[23]
|
Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417-457. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00005756
|
[24]
|
Schweizer, P. (1998). The truly total Turing test. Mind and Machines, 8, 263-272. doi:10.1023/A:1008229619541
|
[25]
|
Stanley, J. (2005). Language in context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
|
[26]
|
Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 1950.
|
[27]
|
Turing, A. M. (1951). Can digital computers think. BBC 3rd programme. In B. J. Copeland (Ed.), The essential Turing, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
http://www.turingarchive.org/browse.php/B/5
|
[28]
|
Wilks, Y. (1986). Default reasoning and self-knowledge. Proceedings of the IEEE, 74, 1399-1404. doi:10.1109/PROC.1986.13640
|
[29]
|
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). The philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.
|
[30]
|
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.
|