The Theory of Membership Degree of Γ-Conclusion in Several n-Valued Logic Systems ()
1. Introduction
Fuzzy logic is the theoretical foundation of fuzzy control. Spurred by the success in its applications, especially in fuzzy control, fuzzy logic has aroused the interest of many famous scholars, a series of important results have been created in documents [1-5]. For the sake of reasoning, we have to choose a subset
of well-formed formulas, which can reflect come essential properties, as the axioms of the logical system and we then deduce the so-called
-conclusion through some reasonable inference rules [6-9]. So, a natural question then arises: how to judge whether or not a general formula
is a conclusion of a given theory
, or to what extend the formula
is a conclusion of
? It is basic problem to judge one thing belong to one kind in artificial intelligence. As is well known, human reasoning is approximate rather than precise in nature. we basic starting point is to establish graded version of basic logical notions. In order to establish a solid foundation for fuzzy reasoning, professor G. J. Wang proposed the concept of root of theory [3], J. C. Zhang proposed the concept of generalized root of theory [10,11], in propositional logic systems. The graded description and properties of formulas
being
-conclusion were discussed. And provide its algorithm of membership degree of formulas A is a
-conclusion, by the constructions of theory root in the above-mentioned logic systems.
2. Preliminaries
It is well known that different implication operators and valuation lattices
(i.e., the set of truth degrees for logic) determine different logic systems (see [12]). Here valuation lattices is
and three popularly used implication operators and the correspond ing t-norms defined as follows:



These three implication operators
and
are called Łukasiewicz implication operator
, Gödel implication operator
, and the
-implication operator
, respectively. The t-norm, which corresponds to
-implication operator
, is called also Nilpotent Minimumtnorm [6]. If we fix a t-norm
above we then fix a propositional calculus (whose set of truth values is
):
is taken for the truth function of the strong conjunction &, the residuum
of
becomes the truth function of the implication operator and R(.,0) is the truth function of the negation. In more details, we have the following definitions.
Definition 1 [7,8]. The propositional calculus
given by a t-norm
has the set
of propositional variables
and connectives
. The set
of well-formed formulas in
is defined inductively as follows: each propositional variable is a formula; if
,
are formulas, then
,
and
are all formulas.
Definition 2 [8,9,13]. The formal deductive systems of
given by
corresponding to
and
, are called Łukasiewicz n-valued logic systems
,
n-valued logic systems
, and the
nvalued logic systems
, respectively.
Define in the above-mentioned logic systems
(1)
and in the corresponding algebras 
(2)
where
is the t-norm defined on
.
Remark 1. It is easy to verify that the following assertions are true:
(1) in
,
for every
.
(2) in
,
for every
and
.
(3) in
, for every
.
Definition 3 [7,8]. (1) A homomorphism
of type
from
into the valuation lattice
, i.e.
, is called an R-valuation of
. The set of all R-valuations will be denoted by
.
(2) A formula
is called a tautology w.r.t.
if
holds.
Remark 2 [8,13]. It is not difficult to verify in the above-mentioned three logic systems that
, and
for every valuation
. Moreover, one can check in
and
that
and
are logically equivalent.
Definition 4 [8]. Assume that
is a formula generated by propositional variables
through connectives
. Substitute
for
in
and keep the logic connectives in
unchanged but explain them as the corresponding operators defined on the valuation lattice
. The we get a function
and call
the truth degree function of
.
Definition 5 [7,8]. (1) A subset of
is called a theory.
(2) Let
be a theory,
. A deduction of
from
, in symbols,
, is a finite sequence of formulas
such that for each
is an axiom of
, or
, or there are
such that
follows from
and
by MP. Equivalently, we say that
is a conclusion of
(or
-conclusion). The set of all conclusions of
is denoted by
. By a proof of
we shall henceforth mean a deduction of
from the empty set. We shall also write
in place of
and call
a theorem.
It is easy for the reader to check the following Proposition 1.
Proposition 1. Let
be a theory and
If
then there exist a finite subset of
say,
such that
.
Theorem 1 (Generalized deduction theorems) [7, 8,12]. Suppose that
is a theory,
, then
(1) in
,
iff
s. t.
.
(2) in
,
iff
.
(3) in
,
iff
.
Definition 6 [8,13]. Suppose that
is a formula of
containing m atomic formulas
, and
be the truth degree function of
. Then

is called the truth degree of
, where
is the cardinal of set
.
Theorem 2. Suppose that
and
, then in
and 
iff
is a tautology i.e.,
.
Proof. Assume that
. Since
then
. By definite,
, thus
i.e.,
,
, then
is a tautology. Conversely, assume that A is a tautology i.e.,
, then
, so
. This completes the proof.
Theorem 3 [8]. Suppose that
, then in
,
iff
is a tautology, i.e.,
.
Theorem 4. Suppose that
. If for every
, then
.
Proof. Suppose that
and
are all a formulas of
containing
atomic formulas
, it follows from
that

and

hence
.
It is easy to verify that

then
.
3. Properties of the Roots of Theories
Definition 7 [3]. Suppose that
is a theory,
. If for every
we have
, then
is called the root of
.
Theorem 5. Suppose that
is a finite theory, say
, then
(1) in 
is a root of
;
(2) in
,
is a root of
;
(3) in
,
is a root of
.
Proof. (1) It following form references [4] that
, for every
, there exist
such that
by Theorem 1. It is easy to check that
by Remark 1, it following from
that
where
, thus
by Hypothetical, this shows that
is a root of
.
(2) It following form references [4] that
, for every
, it following from Theorem 1 that
, since
and
are provably equivalent, and so is
. This shows
is a root of
.
(3) It following from references [4] that
for every
, we get
by Theorem 1, it is easy to verify that
and
are provably equivalent, hence
and
are provably equivalent, and so is
. This shows that
is a root of
.
4. Membership Degree of Formulas A Is Γ-Conclusion
In following, let us first take an analysis on the conditions of formulas A is a
-conclusion in
. Suppose that
is a theory and A is a
-conclusion , it follows from Proposition 1 and Theorem 1 that there exit a finite string of formulas
and
such that
holds, i.e., the formula
is a theorem of
, let
, hence
is a tautology, it follows from Theorem 2 that
. Conversely, if there exist a
-conclusion
such that
, then following from Theorem 2 that
is a tautology, thus
is a theorem of
, i.e.,
holds and
, we have that
by MP, i.e.,
is a
-conclusion. Moreover, the larger the membership degree of such formulas are, the more closer A is to be
-conclusion. Hence it is natural and reasonable for us using the supremum of truth degree of all formulas with the form
where
to measure A is a
-conclusion.
Definition 8. Suppose that
is a theory,
. Define

then
is called the membership degree of formulas A is a
-conclusion.
It is easy to verify that
and following Proposition 2 by Definition 8.
Proposition 2. In
,
and
If A is a
-conclusion, then
.
Theorem 6. In
,
and
, if
is a finite theory, say
, then A is a
-conclusion iff
.
Proof. The necessity part by proposition 2, it is only necessary to prove the sufficiency. Let
. For every number
there exist a formulas
such that
by Definition 8.
(1) In
, it follows from Theorem 5 that
is a root of
and
hold. Hence for every
we have
it follows from properties of implication operators that
, since
is arbitrary, we have
, thus
is a tautology, and
is a theorem , together with the result
, then
by MP, i.e., 
(2) In
, notice that
is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) In
, notice that
is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1). In fact
is a theorem by Definition 7, hence
we have
and
, thus
,
holds, then
is a theorem , together with the result
we have
by MP. The proof is completed.
Theorem 7. Suppose that
, then
(1) in
,
;
(2) in
,
;
(3) in
,
.
Proof. (1) Since
is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence for every
we have
. Thus for every
,
, and
holds, then
by Theorem 4. It follows from
that
i.e.,
.
(2) Notice that in
,
is a root of
by Theorem 5, the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) Notice that in
,
is a root of
by Theorem 5, the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
Theorem 8. Suppose that
is a infinite theory. Then
(1) in
,
;
(2)
,
;
(3) in
,
.
Proof. (1) For every
, it following from Proposition 1 that there exist a finite string of formulas
such that
It follows from Theorem 1 that
is a theorem, hence
is a tautology by completeness theorem, and for every
,
, we have
by Theorem 4.
It following form references [14] that
, then
.
(2) Notice that in
,
by Remark 1, the Proof of (2) is similar to that the Proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) Notice that in
,
and
is Provably equivalent, the Proof of (3) is similar to that the Proof of (1) and so is omitted.
Theorem 9. Suppose that
is a theory,
and
, then 
Proof. (1) If
we get
, then 
(2) If
we get
and
, for any given positive number
such that
and
there exists formulas
such that
and
. It follows from properties of Regular implication operators that
and
It is easy to verify that
and
are provably equivalent (i.e., logically equivalent), hence
. It follows from the theory of truth degrees of formulas and
that
.
Bucas
and
are provably equivalent (i.e., logically equivalent), hence
, it is easy to verify that
then
by the definition of the membership degree of formulas.
Example 1. Suppose that
In
,
and
, compute
respectively.
Solution. (1) In
, assume that
Since
and

thus

and

We have
and
hence
then
.
(2) In
, assume that
Since
, and

thus

then

then
.
(3) In
, assume that
Since
, and



thus

then 
Example 2. Suppose that
, in
, compute 
Solution. (1) Assume that
Since
, and






thus
, then p2
is a
-conclusion.
NOTES